The Logic of the Living Present Experience, Ordering, Onto-Poiesis of Culture

Some might ask "Why Locke's theory of knowledge now?" Though appreciated for his social philosophy, Locke has been criticized for his work in the field of epistemology ever since the publication of the Essay. It is even as if Locke serves only as an example of how not to think. When p...

Full description

Bibliographic Details
Other Authors: Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa (Editor)
Format: eBook
Language:English
Published: Dordrecht Springer Netherlands 1995, 1995
Edition:1st ed. 1995
Series:Analecta Husserliana, The Yearbook of Phenomenological Research
Subjects:
Online Access:
Collection: Springer Book Archives -2004 - Collection details see MPG.ReNa
LEADER 03108nmm a2200337 u 4500
001 EB000716417
003 EBX01000000000000000569499
005 00000000000000.0
007 cr|||||||||||||||||||||
008 140122 ||| eng
020 |a 9789401104630 
100 1 |a Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa  |e [editor] 
245 0 0 |a The Logic of the Living Present  |h Elektronische Ressource  |b Experience, Ordering, Onto-Poiesis of Culture  |c edited by Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka 
250 |a 1st ed. 1995 
260 |a Dordrecht  |b Springer Netherlands  |c 1995, 1995 
300 |a IX, 312 p  |b online resource 
505 0 |a One Constitutive Ordering: Experience and Objectivity -- Idea and Thing: The Deep Structure of Locke’s Theory of Knowledge -- Two The Logic of the Living Present -- Translator’s Introduction -- Dialectical Logic as the General Logic of Temporalization -- Three The Basic Grammar of Intercultural Texts -- Phenomenology, the Question of Rationality and the Basic Grammar of Intercultural Texts -- Four The Constitutive Foundation of Culture: Categories -- The Doctrine of Categories and the Topology of Concern: Prolegomena to an Ontology of Culture -- Index of Names 
653 |a Philosophy, Modern 
653 |a Philosophical Traditions 
653 |a History 
653 |a Phenomenology  
653 |a Philosophy of mind 
653 |a Phenomenology 
653 |a Philosophy of Mind 
041 0 7 |a eng  |2 ISO 639-2 
989 |b SBA  |a Springer Book Archives -2004 
490 0 |a Analecta Husserliana, The Yearbook of Phenomenological Research 
028 5 0 |a 10.1007/978-94-011-0463-0 
856 4 0 |u https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-0463-0?nosfx=y  |x Verlag  |3 Volltext 
082 0 |a 142.7 
520 |a Some might ask "Why Locke's theory of knowledge now?" Though appreciated for his social philosophy, Locke has been criticized for his work in the field of epistemology ever since the publication of the Essay. It is even as if Locke serves only as an example of how not to think. When people criticize Locke, they usually cite the hostile commen­ taries of Berkeley, Kant, Husserl, or Sellars. But, one might ask, are they not all so eager to show the excellence of their own epistemo­ logical views that they distort and underestimate Locke's thought? Russell aptly noted in his History of Western Philosophy that: No one has yet succeeded in inventing a philosophy at once credible and self-consis­ tent. Locke aimed at credibility, and achieved it at the expense of consistency. Most of the great philosophers have done the opposite. A philosophy which is not self-consis­ tent cannot be wholly true, but a philosophy which is self-consistent can very well be wholly false. The most fruitful philosophies have contained glaring inconsistencies, but for that very reason have been partially true. There is no reason to suppose that a self­ consistent system contains more truth than one which, like Locke's, is obviously more or less wrong. (B. Russell, A History of Western Philosophy [New York: Simon and Schuster, 1945], p. 613. ) Here Russell is uncommonly charitable with Locke